Michael Polanyi: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Chris Goodman
m (Entry for Michael Polanyi)
 
mNo edit summary
 
(15 intermediate revisions by 8 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
[[Image:Michaelpolanyi1.jpg|right|thumb]]
{{subpages}}
'''Michael Polanyi''' (born '''Polányi Mihály''') ([[March 11]], [[1891]] [[February 22]], [[1976]]) was a [[Hungary|Hungarian]]–[[United Kingdom|British]] [[polymath]] whose thought and work extended across [[physical chemistry]], [[economics]], and [[philosophy]].  He was a [[Fellow of the Royal Society]] and a Fellow of [[Merton College, Oxford]].
'''Michael Polanyi''' (born '''Polányi Mihály''') (March 11, 1891 – February 22, 1976) was a Hungarian–British polymath who made original contributions to physical chemistry, economics, and philosophy.  He was both a Fellow of the [[Royal Society]] and a Fellow of [[Merton College, Oxford]].


==Early life==
==Early life==


Michael was born into a [[Jew|Jewish]] family in [[Budapest]]. His older brother [[Karl Polanyi|Karl]] became a famous [[economist]]. Their father was an [[engineer]] and [[entrepreneur]] whose volatile fortunes in [[railway]] speculation motivated Polanyi to seek financial stability through a career in [[medicine]]. He graduated in [[1913]], and shortly afterwards served as a physician in the [[Austria-Hungary|Austro-Hungarian]] army during [[World War I]], but was hospitalised, and during his convalescence wrote what became a doctorate in physical chemistry from the [[Eötvös Loránd University|University of Budapest]] (with [[Gusztáv Buchböck]]) in [[1917]].
Michael was born into a secular [[Jew|Jewish]] family in [[Budapest]]. His older brother Karl became a famous economist. Their father was an engineer and railway entrepreneur whose bankruptcy motivated Polanyi to seek financial stability through a career in medicine. He graduated in 1913, and served in the Austro-Hungarian army during World War I, but was hospitalised, and during his convalescence wrote what became a doctorate in physical chemistry from the University of Budapest (with Gusztáv Buchböck) in 1917.


In [[1920]], he emigrated to [[Germany]] to work as a chemist at the [[Kaiser Wilhelm Institute|Kaiser Wilhelm Institute for Fiber Chemistry]] in [[Berlin]]. There, he married Magda Elizabeth in a [[Roman Catholic]] ceremony. In [[1929]], Magda gave birth to a son [[John Charles Polanyi|John]], who went on to win a [[Nobel Prize]] in chemistry. With the coming to power in 1933 of the [[Nazism|Nazi]] party Polanyi took up a position as Professor of Physical Chemistry at the [[University of Manchester]]. As a consequence of his shift of interest from chemistry to economics to philosophy Manchester created a chair in [[Social Science]] (1948-58) for him.
In 1920, he emigrated to Germany and ended up working as a research chemist, and in 1926 a professor, at the Kaiser Wilhelm Institute for Fiber Chemistry in Berlin. There, he married Magda Elizabeth in a [[Roman Catholicism|Roman Catholic]] ceremony. In 1929, Magda gave birth to a son [[John Charles Polanyi|John]], who went on to win a [[Nobel Prize]] in chemistry. With the coming to power in 1933 of the [[Nazism|Nazi]] party Polanyi took up a position as Professor of Physical Chemistry at the University of Manchester in England. As a consequence of a shift in his interests from chemistry to economics and philosophy Manchester created a chair in [[Social Science]] (1948-58) for him.


==Physical chemistry==
==Physical chemistry==
Polanyi's scientific interests were diverse, embracing [[chemical kinetics]], [[x-ray diffraction]] and the absorption of [[gas]]es at [[solid]] [[surface]]s.
Polanyi's scientific interests were diverse, embracing [[chemical kinetics]], [[x-ray diffraction]] and the absorption of gases at solid surfaces.


In [[1934]], Polanyi, roughly contemporarily with [[Geoffrey Ingram Taylor|G. I. Taylor]] and [[Egon Orowan]] realised that the [[plasticity (physics)|plastic]] deformation of [[ductile]] materials could be explained in terms of the theory of [[dislocation]]s developed by [[Vito Volterra]] in [[1905]]. The insight was critical in developing the modern science of [[solid mechanics]].
In 1934, Polanyi, at the same time as [[Geoffrey Ingram Taylor|G. I. Taylor]] and [[Egon Orowan]] realised that the [[plasticity (physics)|plastic]] deformation of [[ductile]] materials could be explained in terms of the theory of [[dislocation]]s developed by [[Vito Volterra]] in 1905. The insight was critical in developing the modern science of [[solid mechanics]].


==Philosophy of science==
==Philosophy of science==
From the mid-[[1930s]], Polanyi began to articulate his opposition to the prevailing [[positivism (philosophy)|positivist]] account of science, arguing that it failed to recognise the part played by [[tacit knowing]] and the [[creativity|creative]] role played by the [[imagination]]. Tacit knowledge and [[explicit knowledge]] were held coefficient, coexistent and indivisible.
From the mid-1930s, Polanyi began to articulate his opposition to the prevailing [[positivism (philosophy)|positivist]] account of science, arguing that it failed to recognise the the role which commitment and [[tacit knowing]] play in science.  


Polanyi viewed [[positivism (philosophy)|positivism]] as encouraging the direction of scientific research by the State. He drew attention to what happened to genetics in the [[Soviet Union]], once the doctrines of [[Trofim Lysenko]] gained political approval. Polanyi, like his friend [[Friedrich Hayek]], supplied reasons why it is desirable to live within a free society.
Polanyi argued that [[positivism (philosophy)|positivism]] encouraged the assumption that scientific research ought to be directed by the State. Polanyi, like his friend [[Friedrich Hayek]], notes the role which [[spontaneous order]] plays in the formation of social orders, and unlike Hayek he also draws attention to the role which commitments play in the formation and maintenance of communities.


Polanyi embraced the existence of objective truth (''Personal Knowledge'', p. 16). However, he criticised a common misunderstanding of the [[scientific method]], namely, the notion that the scientific method is itself an objective discovery process or somehow leads to objective knowledge.
Polanyi rejected the assumption that truth is a mechanical product of method, because all methods rely upon commitments made by interpretors, which in turn rely upon their tacit awareness. The fact that we know more than we can articulate endorses the assumption that knowledge can be passed on by non-explicit means, via apprenticeship. Our tacit awareness is not wholly grounded by interpretative practices however, it is how we encounter realities, and is the ground upon which we rely when giving words meaning.  


Instead, he argued that knowing is personal. A scientist's personal skills, biases, and passions play an important and necessary role in the discovery process. In particular, a chief measure of a scientist's skill is his or her ability to notice and choose problems for investigation (i.e., to formulate hypotheses) that have a high chance of yielding valuable discoveries. Moreover, all observation of the universe is personal, and is influenced by individual biases, human error, and the limits of the observer's knowledge. No human observer can remove humanity from the observation (and to formulate theories as though this were possible leads to conclusions that are absurd because they overlook the existence and influence of humanity and the scientist's biases).  
Polanyi argued that all knowing is personal. Our skills and passions play a necessary part in knowing. Our comprehension of our experience is influenced by our assumptions, but it does not follow that knowledge claims have no objective validity. They may be subjective, but only when they are false.  


The scientific method is valuable in that it provides a systematic means of verification. But the fact that many hypotheses once thought ''proven,'' such as Newton's Laws, are later shown to be limited or even incorrect, is by itself proof that the scientific method can only yield ''insight'' into objective truth, and not the final objective truth, itself.  
His epistemological ideas are most fully expressed in the [[Gifford lectures]] he gave in 1951–52 at the University of Aberdeen which resulted in the book ''Personal Knowledge''. and he influenced, amongst others, [[Thomas Kuhn]], [[Paul Feyerbend]] and [[Imre Lakatos]].


Polanyi's ''personal knowledge'' is characterized by, among other things:
In his later work he reflected upon the structure of what he called the "tacit integration" i.e. the way in which conscious agents generate a focus of attention by relying upon their (largely tacit) subsidiary awareness. He explored the implications of this structure for 1) Perception 2) Tool Use 3) Semantics and 4) Ontology. He characterised the universe as consisting of emergent levels, each constrained both by the lower level properties which render it possible, and higher level boundary conditions.
* the individual scientist's ''ability to perceive'' opportunities for valuable discovery -- partly a learned skill, and partly a personal aptitude ("It is of the essence of the scientific method to select for verification hypotheses having a ''high'' chance of being true. To select good questions for investigation is the mark of scientific talent...." ''Personal Knowledge,'' p. 30);
* the scientist's ''belief'' that the hypothesis is correct and will shed light on some aspect of "rationality in nature" -- importantly, the scientist holds this belief ''before'' validating the hypothesis, making this belief in some sense like faith, and strong enough to lead the scientist to commit to the hypothesis;
* the scientist's personal commitment to investigating his or her hypothesis, which he or she demonstrates by investing valuable time and resources in the investigation, and by staking his or her reputation on the claimed result;
* the notion that we know more than we can articulate; and make our commitment towards knowledge confirmation in an indeterminate future.
 
Polanyi acknowledged the importance of inherited practices ([[tradition]]). The fact that we know more than we can clearly articulate contributes to the conclusion that much knowledge is passed on by non-explicit means, such as [[apprenticeship]] (observing a master, and then practicing under the master's guidance).
 
Polanyi's philosophical ideas are most fully expressed in the [[Gifford lectures]] he gave in 1951–52 at the [[University of Aberdeen]] which resulted in the book ''Personal Knowledge''. These ideas would influence the thought and work of [[Thomas Kuhn]] in the [[1960s]].


==Economics==
==Economics==
Polanyi applied his philosophy of science to the field of economics in his 1951 book, ''The Logic of Liberty,'' a collection of essays most of which had been published in the 1940s. He elaborated on the connections in a 1962 article, "The Republic of Science: Its Political and Economic Theory" in ''Minerva''.<ref>[http://www.compilerpress.atfreeweb.com/Anno%20Polanyi%20Republic%20of%20Science%201962.htm in ''Minerva'' Volume 1: 1962 pp54-74.]</ref><ref>The article can also be viewed [http://www.missouriwestern.edu/orgs/polanyi/mp-repsc.htm here].</ref> Polanyi extrapolated his conclusions about the structure of liberty from within the context of science.
His 1951 book, ''The Logic of Liberty,'' is a collection of essays which link the practice of science with the practices which sustain a free society. He noted that central planning within modern economies is impossible, because central planners cannot make all the adjustments that render it possible. As a consequence of the fact that it is [[polycentric]], a free market however can generate a spontaneous order which is able to co-ordinate the various demands. Polanyi argued that scientists respond to each other in ways that are similar to the way in which individuals coordinate with each other in the [[market (economics)|market]]. Scientists operate however within the constraints supplied by the commitments which generate and sustain their various communities of specialists. He summarised the connections in a 1962 article, "The Republic of Science: Its Political and Economic Theory" in ''Minerva''.<ref>[http://www.compilerpress.atfreeweb.com/Anno%20Polanyi%20Republic%20of%20Science%201962.htm in ''Minerva'' Volume 1: 1962 pp54-74.]</ref><ref>The article can also be viewed [http://www.missouriwestern.edu/orgs/polanyi/mp-repsc.htm here].</ref>  


Polanyi noted that scientists cooperate with each other, or "self coordinate," in a way similar to that in which individuals coordinate in the [[free market]]. Even though each scientist pursues his own goals, the scientist reacts to the limited available knowledge produced by nearby, relevant actors. This tends to reduce redundant activity and channel resources to the newest and most valuable discoveries, and away from dead-end research.
Scientists, like [[entrepreneurs]], require freedom to pursue their ends. In ''The Republic of Science,'' Polanyi emphasises the importance of scientists having the freedom to pursue truth as an end in itself i.e. independent of any social objectives:
 
He believed that a structure of liberty most readily propels both economic and scientific advancement. Both his belief that scientists personally commit to their own beliefs (hypotheses) and his belief that individual scientists self-coordinate led to this conclusion. Scientists, like [[entrepreneurs]], require the freedom to pursue discoveries of their own volition, and for their own reasons. Moreover, they must be free to react to the claims and knowledge put forth by their peers. In ''The Republic of Science,'' Polanyi thus urged societies to allow the freedom to pursue science for its own sake:


<blockquote>
<blockquote>
Line 52: Line 41:
</blockquote>
</blockquote>


Indeed, much of his writing criticized government planning of scientific inquiry as stifling, because it tends to punish scientists for pursuing their own hunches as opposed to the agenda of the state.
He opposed government direction of scientific inquiry, on the grounds that central planning is inferior to a system in which inquirers operate freely within the constraints supplied by the commitments which accompany membership of the scientific community. He implied that this also applies to other dedicated communities e.g. the legal community.


==Family==
==His Family==
Michael Polanyi's son, [[John Charles Polanyi]], is a Professor of Chemistry at the [[University of Toronto]], Canada. In 1986 John Polanyi was awarded the [[Nobel Prize in Chemistry]].<ref>http://www.utoronto.ca/jpolanyi</ref>
Michael Polanyi's son, [[John Charles Polanyi]], is a Professor of Chemistry at the University of Toronto, Canada. In 1986 he was awarded the [[Nobel Prize in Chemistry]].<ref>http://www.utoronto.ca/jpolanyi</ref>
 
==See also==
*[[Tacit knowledge]]
*[[Knowledge management]]


==References==
==References==
{{reflist}}
{{reflist}}[[Category:Suggestion Bot Tag]]
 
==Bibliography==
*Polanyi, M (1946) ''Science, Faith, and Society'' ISBN 0-226-67290-5
*Polanyi, M (1951) ''The Logic of Liberty'' ISBN 0-226-67296-4
*Polanyi, M (1964) ''Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy'' ISBN 0-226-67288-3
*Polanyi, M (1967) ''The Tacit Dimension'' ISBN 0-8446-5999-1 (1983 Doubleday reprint)
*Polanyi, M & Prosch, H (1975) ''Meaning'' ISBN 0-226-67294-8
 
==Further reading==
*Richard Gelwick, ''The Way of Discovery, An Introduction to the Thought of Michael Polanyi''.  Eugene, Oregon: Wipf and Stock, 2004, 181, pp. ISBN 1-59244-687-6 (English).
*Sheldon Richmond, ''Aesthetic Criteria: Gombrich and the Philosophies of Science of Popper and Polanyi''. Amsterdam/Atlanta, GA: Rodopi, 1994, 152 pp. ISBN 90-5183-618-X.
*Drusilla Scott, ''Everyman Revived: The Common Sense of Michael Polanyi''.  Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1995, 216 pp. ISBN 0-8028-4079-5.
*William Taussig Scott and Martin X. Moleski, ''Michael Polanyi, Scientist and Philosopher''.  New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2005, 364 pp. ISBN-13-978-0-19-517433-5, ISBN 0-19-517433-X
 
==External links==
{{wikiquote}}
*[http://www.hyle.org/journal/issues/8-2/bio_nye.html Broad biography by Mary Joe Nye]
*[http://web.archive.org/web/20050324091219/http://www.deepsight.org/articles/polanyi.htm Largely philosophical biography] by Phil Mullins, Editor of the Polanyi journal ''Tradition and Discovery''
*[http://www.missouriwestern.edu/orgs/polanyi/ Polanyi Society] home page
*[http://www.erraticimpact.com/~20thcentury/html/polanyi_michael.htm Polanyi resources at erraticimpact.com]
*[http://www.kfki.hu/chemonet/polanyi/9912/contents.html ''Polanyiana'', Volume 8, Number 1-2] published in Budapest.
*[http://www.infed.org/thinkers/polanyi.htm 'Michael Polanyi and tacit knowledge'] by M. K. Smith (2003), the encyclopedia of informal education
 
[[Category:1891 births|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:1976 deaths|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:Jewish scientists|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:Hungarian chemists|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:British chemists|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:British Jews|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:Hungarian economists|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:Hungarian philosophers|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:British philosophers|Polanyi, Michael]]
[[Category:20th century philosophers|Polanyi, Michael]]
 
[[de:Michael Polanyi]]
[[fr:Michael Polanyi]]
[[it:Michael Polanyi]]
[[hu:Polányi Mihály]]
[[nl:Michael Polanyi]]
[[ja:マイケル・ポランニー]]
[[no:Michael Polanyi]]
[[pl:Michael Polanyi]]
[[ru:Полани, Майкл]]
[[sk:Michael Polanyi]]
[[tr:Michael Polanyi]]

Latest revision as of 16:00, 18 September 2024

This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

Michael Polanyi (born Polányi Mihály) (March 11, 1891 – February 22, 1976) was a Hungarian–British polymath who made original contributions to physical chemistry, economics, and philosophy. He was both a Fellow of the Royal Society and a Fellow of Merton College, Oxford.

Early life

Michael was born into a secular Jewish family in Budapest. His older brother Karl became a famous economist. Their father was an engineer and railway entrepreneur whose bankruptcy motivated Polanyi to seek financial stability through a career in medicine. He graduated in 1913, and served in the Austro-Hungarian army during World War I, but was hospitalised, and during his convalescence wrote what became a doctorate in physical chemistry from the University of Budapest (with Gusztáv Buchböck) in 1917.

In 1920, he emigrated to Germany and ended up working as a research chemist, and in 1926 a professor, at the Kaiser Wilhelm Institute for Fiber Chemistry in Berlin. There, he married Magda Elizabeth in a Roman Catholic ceremony. In 1929, Magda gave birth to a son John, who went on to win a Nobel Prize in chemistry. With the coming to power in 1933 of the Nazi party Polanyi took up a position as Professor of Physical Chemistry at the University of Manchester in England. As a consequence of a shift in his interests from chemistry to economics and philosophy Manchester created a chair in Social Science (1948-58) for him.

Physical chemistry

Polanyi's scientific interests were diverse, embracing chemical kinetics, x-ray diffraction and the absorption of gases at solid surfaces.

In 1934, Polanyi, at the same time as G. I. Taylor and Egon Orowan realised that the plastic deformation of ductile materials could be explained in terms of the theory of dislocations developed by Vito Volterra in 1905. The insight was critical in developing the modern science of solid mechanics.

Philosophy of science

From the mid-1930s, Polanyi began to articulate his opposition to the prevailing positivist account of science, arguing that it failed to recognise the the role which commitment and tacit knowing play in science.

Polanyi argued that positivism encouraged the assumption that scientific research ought to be directed by the State. Polanyi, like his friend Friedrich Hayek, notes the role which spontaneous order plays in the formation of social orders, and unlike Hayek he also draws attention to the role which commitments play in the formation and maintenance of communities.

Polanyi rejected the assumption that truth is a mechanical product of method, because all methods rely upon commitments made by interpretors, which in turn rely upon their tacit awareness. The fact that we know more than we can articulate endorses the assumption that knowledge can be passed on by non-explicit means, via apprenticeship. Our tacit awareness is not wholly grounded by interpretative practices however, it is how we encounter realities, and is the ground upon which we rely when giving words meaning.

Polanyi argued that all knowing is personal. Our skills and passions play a necessary part in knowing. Our comprehension of our experience is influenced by our assumptions, but it does not follow that knowledge claims have no objective validity. They may be subjective, but only when they are false.

His epistemological ideas are most fully expressed in the Gifford lectures he gave in 1951–52 at the University of Aberdeen which resulted in the book Personal Knowledge. and he influenced, amongst others, Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerbend and Imre Lakatos.

In his later work he reflected upon the structure of what he called the "tacit integration" i.e. the way in which conscious agents generate a focus of attention by relying upon their (largely tacit) subsidiary awareness. He explored the implications of this structure for 1) Perception 2) Tool Use 3) Semantics and 4) Ontology. He characterised the universe as consisting of emergent levels, each constrained both by the lower level properties which render it possible, and higher level boundary conditions.

Economics

His 1951 book, The Logic of Liberty, is a collection of essays which link the practice of science with the practices which sustain a free society. He noted that central planning within modern economies is impossible, because central planners cannot make all the adjustments that render it possible. As a consequence of the fact that it is polycentric, a free market however can generate a spontaneous order which is able to co-ordinate the various demands. Polanyi argued that scientists respond to each other in ways that are similar to the way in which individuals coordinate with each other in the market. Scientists operate however within the constraints supplied by the commitments which generate and sustain their various communities of specialists. He summarised the connections in a 1962 article, "The Republic of Science: Its Political and Economic Theory" in Minerva.[1][2]

Scientists, like entrepreneurs, require freedom to pursue their ends. In The Republic of Science, Polanyi emphasises the importance of scientists having the freedom to pursue truth as an end in itself i.e. independent of any social objectives:

"...[S]cientists, freely making their own choice of problems and pursuing them in the light of their own personal judgment, are in fact cooperating as members of a closely knit organization. ...

"Such self-co-ordination of independent initiatives leads to a joint result which is unpremeditated by any of those who bring it about. Their co-ordination is guided as by an "invisible hand" towards the joint discovery of a hidden system of things. Since its end-result is unknown, this kind of co-operation can only advance stepwise, and the total performance will be the best possible if each consecutive step is decided upon by the person most competent to do so. ...

"Any attempt to organize the group ... under a single authority would eliminate their independent initiatives and thus reduce their joint effectiveness to that of the single person directing them from the centre. It would, in effect, paralyse their cooperation."

He opposed government direction of scientific inquiry, on the grounds that central planning is inferior to a system in which inquirers operate freely within the constraints supplied by the commitments which accompany membership of the scientific community. He implied that this also applies to other dedicated communities e.g. the legal community.

His Family

Michael Polanyi's son, John Charles Polanyi, is a Professor of Chemistry at the University of Toronto, Canada. In 1986 he was awarded the Nobel Prize in Chemistry.[3]

References